Philosophy on Anti-Realism and Reductionism

 
Anti-realism, reductionism, reference
Reductionist thesis: statements of the given class have a translation to some
reductive
 class of statements, and this translation confers meaning to the
statements of the given class.
Examples: behaviorism, phenomenalism.
Reduction without anti-realism: Frege about directions and parallelism.
Directions are real objects: classes of parallel straight lines.
It eliminates reference (to directions) from statements about directions.
 
 
 
Phenomenalism as anti-realism: just for this reason.
Is it the same case? Can we have 
explicit
 definition for physical objects in
terms of sense-data?
 
Three, main features of realism:
Bivalence, crucial role of reference, truth-conditional meaning-theory.
 
Reductionism gives up (?) the second one, but may keep the first and the third.
?
 
Reductive thesis: (Not necessarily a translation, but) a statement of the given
class is made true (if it is true) by some statement or class of statements of the
reductive class. This relation determines the meaning of any statement of the
given class.
Types of reductive theses without reductionism:
(i) A weaker form of phenomenalism: A statement about material objects is
made true by an infinite manifold of sense-datum statements.
(ii) The language of the reductive class cannot be given independently of the
language of the given class.
Example: mathematical constructivism. A theorem T is made true by the
statement „We have a proof of T”. We can’t eliminate the original terminology of
the theorems by translating them into statements about possessing proofs.
Another example: statements in the past tense are made true by statements
about present evidence.
(iii) We cannot effectively identify the member of the reductive class responsible
for the truth of some statement of the given class.
Example: no translation from psychology to neurophysiology (Davidson).
 
Reductive thesis 
may
 lead to rejection of bivalence:
There are (or may be) statements A of the given class s. t. neither A, nor “Not A”
is supported by some statement or set of statements of the reductive class.
 
Sophisticated realism: Every statement of the given class is being made true or
false by some statement or set of statements of the reductive class. Example:
central-state materialism about psychological statements.
 
Irreducibility thesis: no non-trivial general answer can be given to the question
„What makes a statement of the given class true when it is true?”.
Example: mathematical realism.
 
Naive realism: realistic interpretation of the given class + irreducibility thesis.
 
Are 
subjunctive conditionals
  (SCs) allowed in the reductive class?
 
First group: yes (e.g. phenomenalism, behaviorism).
If we were to go to the center of the Sun with a thermometer, we would read 10^7
Kelvin grades on it.
 
Second group: no. E.g. mathematical constructivism.
Anti-realism about the past.
 
Bivalence: problem(s) with the first group.
If it were the case that A, it would be the case that B. (Example above.)
Let us suppose that it supports the statement „The temperature in the center of
the Sun is 10^7 °K”
What should be the support of the statement „ „The temperature in the center of
the Sun is not 10^7 °K”?
Obviously not the negation of the above SC: „… we would not necessarily read
10^7 °K”
Perhaps its opposite: „… we would not read 10^7 °K”
 
Strong bivalence (in the reductive class): one of the 
opposite 
SCs is true.
The 
realist 
may reduce the SCs to indicative (categorical) statements: „The
temperature in the center of the Sun is/is not 10^7 °K”.
If we accept this sort reduction, then strong bivalence holds. But it is hardly
acceptable on the other way.
There are other possible reductions of SCs: to observations and patterns in
observations. But the don’t justify strong bivalence.
Dummett’s criticism on phenomenalists: they accepted bivalence for material-
object statements (and therefore implicitly accepted strong bivalence for the
underlying SCs).
Hence, phenomenalism is a sort of sophisticated realism, not of full-fledged anti-
realism.
 
A reductive thesis is not a sufficient condition for anti-realism,
but not a necessary one, either.
Example: a (fictional) sort of neutralism about the future.
Neutralism: future tense statements are 
now
 true or false only in virtue of
something that lies in the present (a reductive thesis).
But he does not regard the meanings of future-tense statements as given by the
conditions under which they are (now) true. If they are now true, they are
necessarily 
true.
Outline of a semantic theory for him:
Possible worlds consisting of the present state and past history of the world plus
some possible future history.
True in a world W at 
t
: true in every world that coincides with W up to 
t
.
In this theory the reductive thesis falls out because there is no such thing as
absolute truth of a statement.
Not realist, but objectivist: future-tense statements are determinately true or not
true (at a given world and time).
Three (four) ways to interpret the thesis „a mathematical statement is true only
if there exists a proof of it”:
(0)  Maybe there is a proof although we never shall know it.
       („Exists” understood platonistically. Nonsense.)
(i)
„Exists” understood as concrete, actual existence, i.e. we actually have a
proof. Truth-value changes in time.
(ii)
„Exists” (and „is true”) understood as tenseless, but constructively (We have
or sometimes we shall have a proof of it.) It makes sense to suppose that a
statement is true although we don’t know it.
(iii)
We eliminate the concept of truth and substitute it with the relation „P is a
proof for A” as the central concept of meaning-theory. In this case, no
reductive thesis (because no truth).
We don’t end up with an objectivist theory of mathematical statements. The
meaning of the statement is formulated in terms of our possessing a proof to it.
That is why the reductive thesis is not a substantial component of the theory of
meaning.
Slide Note
Embed
Share

Explore the concepts of anti-realism, reductionism, and reductive theses in philosophical thought, discussing examples like behaviorism and phenomenalism. Delve into the implications for truth and meaning, including considerations on bivalence and reference in statements.

  • Philosophy
  • Anti-Realism
  • Reductionism
  • Truth
  • Meaning

Uploaded on Feb 27, 2025 | 0 Views


Download Presentation

Please find below an Image/Link to download the presentation.

The content on the website is provided AS IS for your information and personal use only. It may not be sold, licensed, or shared on other websites without obtaining consent from the author. Download presentation by click this link. If you encounter any issues during the download, it is possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Anti-realism, reductionism, reference Reductionist thesis: statements of the given class have a translation to some reductive class of statements, and this translation confers meaning to the statements of the given class. Examples: behaviorism, phenomenalism. Reduction without anti-realism: Frege about directions and parallelism. Directions are real objects: classes of parallel straight lines. It eliminates reference (to directions) from statements about directions. ? Phenomenalism as anti-realism: just for this reason. Is it the same case? Can we have explicit definition for physical objects in terms of sense-data? Three, main features of realism: Bivalence, crucial role of reference, truth-conditional meaning-theory. Reductionism gives up (?) the second one, but may keep the first and the third.

  2. Reductive thesis: (Not necessarily a translation, but) a statement of the given class is made true (if it is true) by some statement or class of statements of the reductive class. This relation determines the meaning of any statement of the given class. Types of reductive theses without reductionism: (i) A weaker form of phenomenalism: A statement about material objects is made true by an infinite manifold of sense-datum statements. (ii) The language of the reductive class cannot be given independently of the language of the given class. Example: mathematical constructivism. A theorem T is made true by the statement We have a proof of T . We can t eliminate the original terminology of the theorems by translating them into statements about possessing proofs. Another example: statements in the past tense are made true by statements about present evidence. (iii) We cannot effectively identify the member of the reductive class responsible for the truth of some statement of the given class. Example: no translation from psychology to neurophysiology (Davidson).

  3. Reductive thesis may lead to rejection of bivalence: There are (or may be) statements A of the given class s. t. neither A, nor Not A is supported by some statement or set of statements of the reductive class. Sophisticated realism: Every statement of the given class is being made true or false by some statement or set of statements of the reductive class. Example: central-state materialism about psychological statements. Irreducibility thesis: no non-trivial general answer can be given to the question What makes a statement of the given class true when it is true? . Example: mathematical realism. Naive realism: realistic interpretation of the given class + irreducibility thesis.

  4. Are subjunctive conditionals (SCs) allowed in the reductive class? First group: yes (e.g. phenomenalism, behaviorism). If we were to go to the center of the Sun with a thermometer, we would read 10^7 Kelvin grades on it. Second group: no. E.g. mathematical constructivism. Anti-realism about the past. Bivalence: problem(s) with the first group. If it were the case that A, it would be the case that B. (Example above.) Let us suppose that it supports the statement The temperature in the center of the Sun is 10^7 K What should be the support of the statement The temperature in the center of the Sun is not 10^7 K ? Obviously not the negation of the above SC: we would not necessarily read 10^7 K Perhaps its opposite: we would not read 10^7 K

  5. Strong bivalence (in the reductive class): one of the opposite SCs is true. The realist may reduce the SCs to indicative (categorical) statements: The temperature in the center of the Sun is/is not 10^7 K . If we accept this sort reduction, then strong bivalence holds. But it is hardly acceptable on the other way. There are other possible reductions of SCs: to observations and patterns in observations. But the don t justify strong bivalence. Dummett s criticism on phenomenalists: they accepted bivalence for material- object statements (and therefore implicitly accepted strong bivalence for the underlying SCs). Hence, phenomenalism is a sort of sophisticated realism, not of full-fledged anti- realism.

  6. A reductive thesis is not a sufficient condition for anti-realism, but not a necessary one, either. Example: a (fictional) sort of neutralism about the future. Neutralism: future tense statements are now true or false only in virtue of something that lies in the present (a reductive thesis). But he does not regard the meanings of future-tense statements as given by the conditions under which they are (now) true. If they are now true, they are necessarily true. Outline of a semantic theory for him: Possible worlds consisting of the present state and past history of the world plus some possible future history. True in a world W at t: true in every world that coincides with W up to t. In this theory the reductive thesis falls out because there is no such thing as absolute truth of a statement. Not realist, but objectivist: future-tense statements are determinately true or not true (at a given world and time).

  7. Three (four) ways to interpret the thesis a mathematical statement is true only if there exists a proof of it : (0) Maybe there is a proof although we never shall know it. ( Exists understood platonistically. Nonsense.) (i) Exists understood as concrete, actual existence, i.e. we actually have a proof. Truth-value changes in time. (ii) Exists (and is true ) understood as tenseless, but constructively (We have or sometimes we shall have a proof of it.) It makes sense to suppose that a statement is true although we don t know it. (iii)We eliminate the concept of truth and substitute it with the relation P is a proof for A as the central concept of meaning-theory. In this case, no reductive thesis (because no truth). We don t end up with an objectivist theory of mathematical statements. The meaning of the statement is formulated in terms of our possessing a proof to it. That is why the reductive thesis is not a substantial component of the theory of meaning.

Related


More Related Content

giItT1WQy@!-/#giItT1WQy@!-/#